Biology Worthy of Life
An experiment in revivifying biology
Tags: chromosome/chromatin; chromosome/dynamics; chromosome/in 3D space; DNA; DNA/noncoding; epigenetics; explanation/and causation; gene/genocentrism; gene regulation; genomic_hype; holism; holism/organism as a formed stream; machine idea/code;
When it emerged a few years ago that humans and chimpanzees shared, by some measures, 98 or 99 percent of their DNA, a good deal of verbal hand-wringing and chest-beating ensued. How could we hold our heads up with high-browed, post-simian dignity when, as the New Scientist reported in 2003, “chimps are human”? If the DNA of the two species is more or less the same, and if, as nearly everyone seemed to believe, DNA is destiny, what remained to make us special?
Such was the fretting on the human side, anyway. To be truthful, the chimps didn’t seem much interested. And their disinterest, it turns out, was far more fitting than our angst.
In 1992 Nobel prizewinning geneticist Walter Gilbert wrote that you and I will hold up a CD containing our DNA sequence and say, “Here is a human being; it’s me!” His essay was entitled, “A Vision of the Grail” (Gilbert 1992). Today one can only wonder how we became so invested in the almost sacred importance of an abstract and one-dimensional genetic code — a code so thinly connected to the full-fleshed reality of our selves that its entire import could be captured in a naked and scarcely coherent string of four endlessly repeating letters, like so:
ATGCGATCTGTGAGCCGAGTCTTTAAGTTCATTGACATGCCAACAGAAGGTAAACCT
It’s true that the code, as it was understood at the height of the genomic era, had some grounding in material reality. Each of the four different letters represented one of the four nucleotide bases constituting the DNA sequence. And each group of three successive letters (referred to as a codon) potentially represented an amino acid, a constituent of protein. The idea was that the bases in a protein-coding DNA sequence, or gene, led to the synthesis of the corresponding sequence of amino acids in a protein. And proteins play a decisive role in virtually all living processes. By specifying the production of proteins, genes were presumed bearers of the blueprint, or master program, or molecular instruction book of our lives.
Certainly the idea seemed powerful to those who were enamored of it. In their enthusiasm they gave us countless cellular mechanisms and one revolutionary gene discovery after another — a gene for cancer, a gene for cystic fibrosis (excerpted above), a gene for obesity, a gene for depression, a gene for alcoholism, a gene for sexual preference . . . Building block by building block, genetics was going to show how a healthy human being could be constructed from mindless, indifferent matter.
And yet the most striking thing about the genomic revolution is that the revolution never happened. Yes, it’s been an era of the most amazing technical achievement, marked by an overwhelming flood of new data. Supposed new molecular mechanisms are being detailed weekly. But one might easily think that the meaning of it all — how we can understand the integrity and unified functioning of the living cell — has been more obscured than illumined by the torrent of data. It’s true that we are gaining, even if largely by trial and error, certain manipulative powers. But what about our clouded vision of the Grail? “Many of us in the genetics community”, write Linda and Edward McCabe, authors of DNA: Promise and Peril, “sincerely believed that DNA analysis would provide us with a molecular crystal ball that would allow us to know quite accurately the clinical futures of our individual patients”. Unfortunately, as they and many others now acknowledge, the reality did not prove so straightforward.
As minor tokens of the changing consciousness among biologists, one could cite articles from this past year in the world’s two premier scientific journals, each reflecting upon the discovery of the “gene for cystic fibrosis”. THE PROMISE OF A CURE: 20 YEARS AND COUNTING — so ran the headline in Science, followed by this slightly sarcastic gloss: “The discovery of the cystic fibrosis gene brought big hopes for gene-based medicine; although a lot has been achieved over two decades, the payoff remains just around the corner” (Couzin-Frankel 2009). An echo quickly came from Nature, without the sarcasm: ONE GENE, TWENTY YEARS — “When the cystic fibrosis gene was found in 1989, therapy seemed around the corner. Two decades on, biologists still have a long way to go” (Pearson 2009).
The story has been repeated for one gene after another, which may be part of the reason why molecular biologist Tom Misteli offered such a startling postscript to the unbounded optimism of the Human Genome Project. “Comparative genome analysis and large-scale mapping of genome features”, he wrote in the journal Cell, “shed little light onto the Holy Grail of genome biology, namely the question of how genomes actually work” in living organisms (Misteli 2007).
But is this surprising? The human body is not a mere implication of clean logical code in abstract conceptual space, but rather a play of complexly shaped and intricately interacting physical substances and forces. Yet the four genetic letters, in the researcher’s mind, became curiously detached from their material matrix. In many scientific discussions it hardly would have mattered whether the letters of the “Book of Life” represented nucleotide bases or completely different molecular combinations. All that counted were certain logical correspondences between code and protein together with a few bits of regulatory logic — all buttressed, to be sure, by the massive weight of an unsupported assumption: somehow, by neatly executing an immaculate, computer-like DNA logic, the organism would fulfill its destiny as a living creature. The details could be worked out later. That the enlivened physical being of the gene and chromosome must have more to contend with, and more to contribute, than obedience to a one-dimensional code marking out a causal connection linking DNA and protein — this certainty didn’t seem to burden many geneticists unduly.
The misdirection in all this badly needs elaborating — a task I hope to advance here. As for the differences between humans and chimpanzees, the only wonder is that so many were exercised by the problem. If we had wanted to compare ourselves to chimps, we could have done the obvious and direct and scientifically respectable thing: we could have observed ourselves and chimps, noting the similarities and differences. Not such a strange notion, really — unless one is so transfixed by a code abstracted from human and chimp that one comes to prefer it to the organisms themselves — the organisms that are the only possible source for whatever legitimacy and physical meaning the abstraction possesses.
I’m not aware of any pundit who, brought back to reality from the realm of code-fixated cerebration, would have been so confused about the genetic comparison as to invite a chimp home for dinner to discuss world politics. If we had been looking to ground our levitated theory in scientific observation, we would have known that the proper response to the code similarity in humans and chimps was: “Well, so much for the central, determining role we’ve been assigning to our genes”.
Thankfully, that seems to be where biology is getting to these days. We are progressing into a post-genomic era — often referred to as the era of epigenetics.
Epigenetics most commonly refers to heritable changes in gene activity not accounted for by alterations or mutations in actual DNA sequences. But in order to understand the important developments now under way in biology, it’s more useful to take the word in its broadest sense as referring to “how genes are employed by their living context”. To realize the full significance of the truth so often remarked in the technical literature today — namely, that context matters — is indeed to embark upon a revolutionary adventure. It means reversing one of the most deeply engrained habits within science — the habit of explaining the whole as the result of its parts. If an organic context really does rule its parts in the way molecular biologists are beginning to recognize, then we have to learn to speak about that peculiar form of governance, turning our usual causal explanations upside down. We have to learn to explain the part as an expression of a larger, contextual unity.
Historically, an intellectual recoiling from this necessity was what led to an overly narrow concept of the genetic code. The code was supposed to reassure us that something like a computational machine lay beneath the life of the organism. The fixity, precision, and unambiguous logical relations of the code seemed to guarantee its strictly mechanistic performance in the cell. Yet it is this fixity, this notion of a precisely characterizable march from cause to effect — and, more broadly, from gene to trait — that has lately been dissolving more and more into the fluid, dynamic exchange of living processes. Organisms, it appears, must be understood and explained at least in part from above downward, from context to subcontext, from the general laws or character of their being to the never fully independent details. In the end, we can meaningfully apprehend the lowest-level activities only so far as we recognize them to be performances of the whole organism.
A number of apparent paradoxes helped to nudge the molecular biologist toward a more contextualized understanding of the gene. To begin with, the Human Genome Project confirmed a downward revision of the human gene count from 100,000 to somewhere around 21,000. What made the figure startling was the fact that much simpler creatures — for example, a tiny, transparent roundworm — were found to have roughly the same number of genes. More recently researchers have turned up a pea aphid with 34,600 genes and a water flea with 39,000 genes. If genes account for our complexity and make us what we are — well, not even the “chimps are human” advocates were ready to set themselves on the same scale with a water flea. The difference in gene counts required some sort of shift in our understanding.
A second oddity centered on the fact that, upon “deciphering” the genetic Book of Life, we found that our coding scheme made the vast bulk of it read like nonsense. That is, some 98 percent of human DNA was not a carrier of the genetic code at all. It was useless for making proteins. Most of this noncoding DNA was at first dismissed as “junk” — meaningless evolutionary detritus accumulated over the ages. At best it was viewed as a kind of bag of spare parts, borne by cells from one generation to another for possible employment in future genomic innovations. But that’s an awful amount of junk for a cell to have to lug around, duplicate at every cell division, and otherwise manage on a continuing basis.
Another paradox — perhaps the most decisive one — was recognized and wrestled with (and more often just ignored) going back to the early twentieth century. With few exceptions,1 every different type of cell in the human body contains the same chromosomes and the same DNA sequence as the original, single-celled zygote. Yet somehow this zygote manages to differentiate into every manner of tissue — liver, skin, muscle, brain, blood, bone, retina . . . If genes determine the form and substance of the organism, how is it that such radically different cellular architectures result from the same genes? What directs genes in their temporally and spatially varying activity so as to produce the intricately sculpted and complexly differentiated form of a human being? And how can this directing agency be governed by the very genes it directs?
The developmental biologist F. R. Lillie, remarking in 1927 on the contrast between “genes which remain the same throughout life” and a developmental process that “never stands still from germ to old age”, asserted that “Those who desire to make genetics the basis of physiology of development will have to explain how an unchanging complex can direct the course of an ordered developmental stream” (Lillie 1927, pp. 367-8).
Think for a moment about this ordered developmental stream. When a cell of the body divides, the daughter cells can be thought of as “inheriting” traits from the parent cell. The puzzle about this cellular-level inheritance is that, especially during the main period of an organism’s development, it leads to a dramatic, highly directed differentiation of tissues. For example, embryonic cells on a path leading to heart muscle tissue become progressively more specialized. The changes each step of the way are “remembered” (that is, inherited) — but what is remembered is caught up within a process of continuous change. During development you cannot say that “every cell reproduces after its own likeness”.
Over successive generations, cells destined to become a particular type lose their ability to be transformed into any other tissue type. And so the path of differentiation leads from totipotency (the single-celled zygote is capable of developing into every cell of the body), to pluripotency (embryonic stem cells can transform themselves into many, but not all, tissue types during fetal development), to multipotency (blood stem cells can yield red cells, white cells, and platelets), to the final, fully differentiated cell of a particular tissue. In tissues where cell division continues further, the inheritance thereafter may take on a much greater constancy, with like giving rise (approximately) to like.
Cells of the mature heart and brain, then, have inherited entirely different destinies, but the difference in those destinies was not written in their DNA sequences, which remain identical in both organs. If we were stuck in the “chimp equals human” mindset, we would have to say that the brain is the same as the heart.
So what’s going on? Let me summarize it this way. The modest number of human genes compared to the gene counts of much simpler organisms gives us good reason to abandon catchphrases such as “DNA is the Book of Life”. Genes are no more the defining feature of human life than are the proteins that maintain and employ our DNA with such profound effectiveness, or the membranes that so intricately and adaptively structure all the activities of our cells.
Second, the huge amount of non-protein-coding (“junk”) DNA in the human genome gives us good reason to abandon the idea that coding for proteins is the be-all and end-all of DNA. Molecular biologists are in fact rapidly discovering that noncoding sequences play crucial roles in the regulation of gene expression. These sequences — which are never absolutely determinative, and which by themselves can do nothing — offer countless points of entry for the larger cellular environment to “decide” how to employ its DNA.
In other words, the current exploration of the expansive, noncoding portion of our genome encourages us to turn from DNA as the explainer of the organism to DNA as a resource the organism puts to its own use. This already suggests an approach to the third problem. If we ask, “How is it possible for an unchanging complex to explain an ordered developmental stream?” the answer is, “It isn’t possible”. It’s obvious enough that things cannot by themselves explain processes. And we don’t need them to. We need to look to the organism itself as a living activity for an explanation of the different uses to which its DNA is put; the DNA doesn’t explain the organism.
What’s demanded of us is a more living understanding. It is not only that DNA by itself is inadequate to regulate its own genes. What we are finding is that at the molecular level the organism is so dynamic, so densely woven and multidirectional in its causes and effects, that it cannot be explicated as living process through any strictly local investigations. When it begins to appear that “everything does everything to everything” (Dumont and Maenhaut 2001), the search for “regulatory control” necessarily leads to the unified and irreducible functioning of the cell and organism as a whole.
The usual formula has it that DNA makes RNA and RNA makes protein. The DNA double helix forms a kind of spiraling ladder, with pairs of nucleotide bases constituting the rungs of the ladder: a nucleotide base attached to one siderail of the ladder bonds with a base attached to the other siderail. These two bases are normally complementary, so that an A pairs only with a T (and vice versa), just as C and G are paired. Each siderail, with its attached nucleotide bases, is considered a single strand of the double helix. Because the chemical subunits making up the double helix are asymmetrical and oriented oppositely on the two strands, the strands can be said to “point” in opposite directions.
The enzyme that transcribes DNA into RNA must move along the length of a gene in the proper direction, separating the two strands and using one of them as a template for synthesizing an RNA transcript — a transcript that complements the template in much the same way that one DNA strand complements the other. It is by virtue of this complementation that the code for a protein is passed from DNA to RNA. The RNA molecule, however, is commonly single-stranded, unlike DNA. Once formed, it may pass through the nuclear envelope to the cytoplasm, where it is translated into protein.
Or so the usual story runs — which is more or less correct as far as it goes. But let’s look at some of what else must go on in order to make the story happen.
If you arranged the DNA in a human cell linearly, it would extend for nearly two meters. How do you pack all that DNA into a cell nucleus just five or ten millionths of a meter in diameter? According to the usual comparison it’s as if you had to pack 24 miles (40 km) of extremely thin thread into a tennis ball. Moreover, this thread is divided into 46 pieces (individual chromosomes) averaging, in our tennis-ball analogy, over half a mile long. Can it be at all possible not only to pack the chromosomes into the nucleus, but also to keep them from becoming hopelessly entangled?
Obviously it must be possible, however difficult to conceive — and in fact an endlessly varied packing and unpacking is going on all the time. The first thing to realize is that chromosomes do not consist of DNA only. Their actual substance, an intricately woven structure of DNA, RNA, and protein, is referred to as chromatin. Histone proteins, several of which can bind together in the form of an extremely complex histone core particle, are the single most prominent constituent of this chromatin. Every cell contains numerous such core particles — there are some 30 million in a typical human cell — and the DNA double helix, after wrapping a couple of times around one of them, typically extends for a short stretch and then wraps around another one. The core particle with its DNA is referred to as a nucleosome, and between 75 and 90 percent of our DNA is wrapped up in nucleosomes.
But that’s just the first level of packing; it accounts for relatively little of the overall condensation of the chromosomes. If you twist a long, double-stranded rope, you will find the rope beginning to coil upon itself, and if you continue to twist, the coils will coil upon themselves, and so on without particular limit, depending on the fineness and length of the rope. Something like this supercoiling happens with the chromosome, mediated in part by the histone core particles. As a result the core particles, and the DNA along with them, become tightly packed almost beyond comprehension, in a dense, three-dimensional geometry that researchers have yet to visualize in any detail. This highly condensed state, characterizing great stretches of every chromosome, contrasts with other, relatively uncondensed stretches known as open chromatin.
With that background, we can gain our first glimpse of the concerted dynamism in which genes participate. At any one time — and with the details depending on the tissue type and stage of the organism’s development, among other things — some parts of every chromosome are heavily condensed while others are open. Every overall configuration represents a unique balance between constrained and liberated expression of our total complement of 21,000 genes This is because the transcription of genes generally requires an open state; genes in condensed chromatin are largely silenced.
The supercoiling has another direct, more localized role in gene expression. Think again of twisting a rope: depending on the direction of your twist, the two strands of the helix will either become more tightly wound around each other or will be loosened and unwound. (This is independent of the supercoiling, which occurs in either case.) And if, taking a double-stranded rope in hand, you insert a pencil between the strands and force it in one direction along the rope, you will find the strands winding ever more tightly ahead of the pencil’s motion and unwinding behind.
Recall, then, that the enzyme (RNA polymerase) responsible for transcribing DNA into RNA must separate the two strands as it moves along a gene sequence. This is much easier if the supercoiling of the chromatin has already loosened the strands — and harder if the strands are tightened. So in this way the variations in supercoiling along the length of a chromosome either encourage or discourage the transcription of particular genes. Moreover, by virtue of its own activity in moving along the DNA and separating the two strands, RNA polymerase (like the pencil) tends to unwind the strands in the chromosomal region behind it, rendering that region, too, more susceptible to gene expression. There are proteins that detect such changes in torsion propagating along chromatin, and they read the changes as “suggestions” about helping to activate nearby genes (Lavelle 2009; Kouzine et al. 2008).
Picture the situation concretely. Every bodily activity or condition presents its own requirements for gene expression. Whether you are running or sleeping, starving or feasting, getting aroused or calming down, suffering a flesh wound or recovering from pneumonia — in all cases the body and its different cells have specific, almost incomprehensibly complex and changing requirements for differential expression of thousands of genes. And one thing necessary for achieving this expression in all its fine detail is the properly choreographed performance of the chromosomes.
This performance cannot be captured with an abstract code. Interacting with its surroundings, the chromosome belongs as much to a living activity as any other element in its cellular environment. Maybe instead of summoning the image of a rope, I should have invoked a snake, coiling, curling, and sliding over a landscape that is itself in continual movement.
The chromosome, remarks Christophe Lavelle of France’s Curie Institute, “is a plastic polymorphic dynamic elastic resilient flexible nucleoprotein complex” (Lavelle 2009). There are many levels at which we discover significant form and organization in it. Each chromosome, for example, is structured by various means — and never in extremely rigid ways — into functionally significant chromosome domains. We’ve already seen that chromosomes have both condensed and more open regions. The boundaries between these regions are not always well-defined or digitally precise. Simply by residing close to a more compact region, a gene that otherwise would be very actively transcribed might be only intermittently expressed, or even silenced altogether.
Chromosome domains are also established by the twisting forces (torsion) that, as we have seen, are communicated more or less freely along bounded segments of the chromosome. The loci within such a region share a common torsion, and this can attract a common set of regulatory proteins. The torsion also tends to correlate with the level of compaction of the chromatin fiber, which in turn correlates with many other aspects of gene regulation. And even on an extremely small scale, the twisting or untwisting of the short stretches of DNA between nucleosomes by various proteins is presumed to help drive the folding or unfolding of the local chromatin (Travers and Muskhelishvili 2007). All this reminds us that gene regulation is defined less by static elements of logic than by the quality and force of various movements.
There are still other ways that the chromosome reveals itself as a dynamic, complexly structured context. Genes expressed in the same cell type or at the same time, genes sharing common regulatory factors, and genes actively expressed (or mostly inactive) tend to be grouped together. One way such domains could be established is through the binding of the same protein complexes along a region of the chromosome, thereby establishing a common molecular and regulatory environment for the encompassed genes. But it’s important to realize that, like so much in the fluid, living cell, such regions are more a matter of tendency than of absolute rule.
So far we’ve been looking only at the structure of the chromosome itself. But organization at one level of an organism never makes sense except so far as it reflects organization at other levels. The structured chromosome can fulfill its tasks only by participating in — mirroring and being mirrored by — a structured nucleus sharing the same living character.
Every chromosome tends to occupy a characteristic region of the nucleus — a chromosome territory that varies with the tissue type, the stage of the organism’s development, and the life cycle of the individual cell. Chromosomes, or parts of chromosomes, near the center of the nucleus are marked by more intense gene expression, while those near the outer periphery tend to be repressed — although there are major exceptions.
For local regions of a chromosome, this effect of location can be finely tuned to a degree and in ways that currently baffle all attempts at understanding. Spurred by as yet unknown signals, a particular segment of a chromosome will loop out as an open-chromatin “thread” from its primary territory and come together with other looping segments of the same chromosome — often “accompanied by the reorganization of the chromosome neighborhood” (Göndör and Ohlsson 2009). This well-aimed movement brings certain genes and regulatory elements together while keeping other chromosomal loci apart, and in this way properly coordinated gene expression is brought about. Sometimes the fraternizing genes are separated on their chromosome by tens of millions of nucleotide bases (Simonis et al. 2006).
Such chromosome movements, which can be “fast and directed” (Chuang et al. 2006), are now known to bring together genes and regulatory sites on different chromosomes as well — a considerable feat of precise targeting when you consider not only the chromosome-packing problem discussed above, but also the fact that there are billions of nucleotide bases on the human chromosomes. Yet such synchronization of position can be decisive for the expression of particular genes.
Looking at all the coordinated looping and dynamic reorganization of chromosomes, one research team concluded:
Our observations demonstrate that not only active, but also inactive, genomic regions can transiently interact over large distances with many loci in the nuclear space. The data strongly suggest that each DNA segment has its own preferred set of interactions. This implies that it is impossible to predict the long-range interaction partners of a given DNA locus without knowing the characteristics of its neighboring segments and, by extrapolation, the whole chromosome. (Simonis et al. 2006)
So context indeed matters. Moreover, the relevant organization of the cell nucleus involves much more than the chromosomes themselves. There are so-called transcription factories within the nucleus where looping chromosome segments, appropriate regulatory proteins, transcribing enzymes (RNA polymerase), and other substances gather together, presumably making for highly efficient and coordinated gene expression.
Other nuclear functions beside transcription also seem to be localized in this way. But all these specialized locales lack rigid or permanent structure, and are typically marked by rapid turnover of molecules (Osborne et al. 2004; Wachsmuth et al. 2008). It’s almost as if one were looking at something like standing waves in the nucleus. In any case, the lack of well-defined structure in these functional locations contrasts with the cell cytoplasm, which is elaborately subdivided by membranes and populated by numerous organelles. The extraordinary “lightness” and fluidity of the nucleus also provide an interesting contrast to the relative fixity of the DNA sequence.
How the cell manages all these movements in order to bring about just the right expression of just the right genes is hard to fathom. A fairly recent surprise has been the discovery of actin and myosin in connection with some chromosome movements (Albrethsen et al. 2009). These two substances, which play a major role in the contraction of muscles, seem also to provide a kind of “musculature” within the nucleus. Get rid of them, and certain observed movements stop. But they do not seem to form a fixed structure, and little is known about how the movement is actually achieved.
With so much concerted movement going on — not to mention the coiling and packing and unpacking of chromosomes mentioned earlier — how does the cell keep all those “miles of string in the tennis ball” from getting hopelessly tangled? In this case we at least know some of the players addressing the problem. For example, there are enzymes called “topoisomerases”, whose task is to help manage the spatial organization of chromosomes. Demonstrating a spatial insight and dexterity that might amaze those of us who have struggled to sort out tangled masses of thread, these enzymes manage to make just the right local cuts to the strands in order to relieve strain, allow necessary movement of individual genes or regions of the chromosome and prevent a hopeless mass of knots.
Some topoisomerases cut just one strand of the double helix, allow it to wind or unwind around the other strand, and then reconnect the severed ends. This alters the supercoiling of the DNA. Other topoisomerases cut both strands, pass a loop of the chromosome through the gap thus created, and then seal the gap again. (Imagine trying this with miles of string crammed into a tennis ball!) I don't think anyone would claim to have the faintest idea how this is actually managed in a meaningful, overall, contextual sense, although great and fruitful efforts are being made to analyze isolated local forces and “mechanisms”.
In sum: the chromosome is engaged in a highly effective spatial performance. It is a living, writhing, gesturing expression of its cellular environment, and the significance of its gesturing goes far beyond the negative requirement that it be condensed and kept free of tangles. If the organism is to survive, chromosome movements must be well-shaped responses to sensitively discerned needs, resulting in every gene being expressed or not expressed according to the needs of the larger context. The chromosome, along with everything else in the cell, is itself a manifestation of life, not a logic or mechanism explaining life.
It’s not just that DNA is “managed” by the spatial dynamism of the nucleus and the complex structural folding and unfolding of the chromatin matrix. The DNA sequence itself is subject to continual transformation. This is not surprising, given that it must participate in the play of form, force, and movement underlying gene expression.
It happens, for example, that certain nucleotide bases are subject to DNA methylation — the attachment of methyl groups. These small chemical entities are said to “tag” or "mark" the affected bases, a highly significant process that occurs selectively and dynamically throughout the entire genome. Words such as “attach”, “tag”, and “mark”, however, are grossly inadequate, suggesting as they do little more than a kind of coding function whereby we can classify every nucleotide base with a trivial yes-or-no, zero-or-one verdict, depending on the presence or absence of a methyl group. What this leaves out is the actual qualitative change resulting from the chemical transaction.
Part of the problem lies in the mechanistic mindset that always looks for the mere aggregation of parts, as if the methyl group and nucleotide base were discrete Lego blocks added together, one as a tag upon the other. But wherever chemical bonds are formed or broken, we see a true transformation of matter. The result is not a mere aggregation or mixture of the substances that came together, but something entirely new, with different qualities and a different constellation of forces. Think, for example of the difference between hydrogen and oxygen gases on the one hand, and the water that results from their chemical combination, on the other hand.
Of course, there are different kinds of chemical bond, and one small chemical group attached to a vast macromolecule such as the DNA may have mainly a localized effect. But that local effect is not trivial — which is why DNA methylation has become such a major topic in genetics today.
So to think of a methylated cytosine (the nucleotide base most commonly affected) as still the same letter “C” that it was before its methylation, but merely tagged with a methyl group, is to miss the full reality of the situation. What we are really looking at is a metamorphosis of millions of letters of the genetic code under the influence of pervasive and poorly understood cellular processes. And the altered balance of forces represented by all those transformed letters certainly plays with countless possible nuances into the surrounding chromatin, re-shaping in a qualitative way its sculptural qualities and therefore also its expressive potentials.
We are now learning about the extreme consequences of these metamorphoses. In the first place, the transformations of structure brought about by methylation can render DNA locations no longer accessible to the protein transcription factors that might otherwise bind to them and activate the associated genes. Secondly, and perhaps more fundamentally, there are many proteins that do recognize methylated sites and bind specifically to them, recruiting in turn other proteins that restructure the chromatin — typically condensing it and resulting in gene repression.
It would be difficult to overstate the pervasive role of DNA methylation in the organism. In humans, distinctive patterns of DNA methylation are associated with Rett syndrome (a form of autism) and various kinds of mental retardation. Stephen Baylin, a geneticist at Johns Hopkins School of Medicine, says that the silencing, via DNA methylation, of tumor suppressor genes is “probably playing a fundamental role in the onset and progression of cancer. Every cancer that’s been examined so far, that I’m aware of, has this [pattern of] methylation” (quoted in Brown 2008). In an altogether different vein, researchers have found that “DNA methylation is dynamically regulated in the adult nervous system” and is a “crucial step” in memory formation (Miller and Sweatt 2007). It also seems to play a key role in tissue differentiation.
Some patterns of DNA methylation are heritable, leading to a kind of Lamarckian inheritance of acquired characteristics, the study of which is becoming intense today. But by no means are all methylation patterns inherited. For the most part they are not, and for good reason. It would hardly do if tissue-specific patterns of methylation — for example, those in the heart, kidney, or brain — were passed along to the zygote, whose undifferentiated condition is so crucial for its future development in its own terms.
In general, then, the slate upon which all the developmental processes of the adult have been written needs to be wiped clean in order to clear a space for the independent life of the next generation. As part of this slate-cleaning, a restructuring wave of demethylation passes along each chromosome shortly after fertilization, and is completed by the time of implantation in the uterus. Following this, a new methylation occurs, shaped by the embryo itself and giving it a fresh epigenetic start. When, in mammals, the stage of embryonic methylation is blocked artificially, the organism quickly dies.
This structuring and restructuring of DNA by the surrounding life processes is fully as central to a developing organism as the code-conforming DNA sequence.
Countless other molecular interactions play a transformative role with DNA, a few of which will be glancingly touched on below.
We have seen that chromosomes are more than their DNA, with its coded sequence. But even when we restrict our gaze to DNA as such, we find much more than a presumed logic — much more than a one-dimensional array of codons that map to the amino acids of protein. As one group of researchers summarize the matter: There is a “growing body of evidence that the topology and the physical features of the DNA itself is [sic] an important factor in the regulation of transcription” (Dineen et al. 2009). I will try to illustrate this briefly.
Each nucleosome core particle is, as we have seen, enwrapped by a couple of turns of the DNA double helix. This takes some doing, since the double helix has a certain “stiffness”, or resistance to bending. So here is one way DNA manifests its concrete character as a bearer of form: some combinations of nucleotide bases lend themselves more easily to bending than others. These combinations influence where nucleosomes will be positioned along the double-stranded DNA. And the positioning of nucleosomes matters at a highly refined level: a shift in position as little as two or three base pairs can make the difference between an expressed or silenced gene (Martinez-Campa 2004).
Further, not only the exact position of a nucleosome along the double helix, but also the precise rotation of the helix is important. “Rotation” refers to which part of the DNA faces toward a histone surface and which part faces outward. Depending on orientation, the nucleotide bases will be more or less accessible to the various activating and repressing factors that recognize and bind to specific sequences. The orientation in turn depends considerably on the configuration of the local sequence of bases. All of which is to say that among the important meanings of the multivalent language spoken by the genetic sequence are those relating to the distribution of forces in the double helix, which must appropriately complement the forces in nucleosome core particles (which latter, as we will see below, can express themselves with dynamic and endless variation).
The shape of a stretch of DNA matters in a different way as well. There are two grooves (the major and minor grooves) running the length of the DNA double helix, and proteins that recognize an exact sequence of nucleotide bases typically do so in the major groove. However, many proteins bind to DNA in highly selective ways that are not determined by an exact sequence. Recent work has shown that the minor groove may be compressed so as to enhance the local negative electrostatic potential. Regulatory proteins “read” the compression and the electrostatic potential as cues for binding to the DNA. The “complex minor-groove landscape” (Rohs et al. 2009) is affected by the DNA sequence, as well as by associated proteins; however, regulatory factors “reading” the landscape can hardly do so according to a strict digital code. By musical analogy: it’s less a matter of identifying a precise series of notes than of recognizing a melodic motif.
This discovery of the role of the minor groove also helps to solve a puzzle. “The ability to sense the variation in electrostatic potential in DNA”, according to bioinformatics researcher Tom Tullius, “may reveal how a protein could home in on its binding site in the genome without touching every nucleotide” — of which there are billions in every set of human chromosomes. The lesson in all this, Tullius suggests, has to do with what we lose when we simplify DNA to “a one-dimensional string of letters” (Tullius 2009).
It’s remarkable how readily the historical shift from direct observation of organisms to instrumental read-outs of molecular-level processes encouraged a forgetfulness of material form and substance in favor of abstract codes fit for computers.
Distinct combinations of nucleotide bases not only assume different conformations themselves; by virtue of their structure, or pattern of forces, they can also impart different conformations to the proteins that bind to them — and these differences can matter a great deal. A group of California molecular biologists investigated the glucocorticoid receptor, one of many transcription factors that respond to hormones. Noting the general fact that “genes are not simply turned on or off, but instead their expression is fine-tuned to meet the needs of a cell”, the researchers went on to report that the DNA binding sequences for the glucocorticoid receptor at various genes may differ by as little as a single base pair. Receptors alter their conformation in response to such differences, and in this way their own regulatory activity is modulated by the requirements of a particular gene (Meijsing et al. 2009).
Another research team, based in Europe, looked at several different hormone-responding transcription factors. They concluded not only that the DNA sequences to which these proteins were bound imparted conformational changes to the proteins, but also that these changes led to selective recruitment of different co-regulators and perhaps even to distinct restructurings of the local chromatin architecture. The researchers refer to the “subtle information” conveyed by “unique differences” in the DNA sequence, and the consequent “fine-tuning” of the interplay among regulatory factors. “Small variations in DNA sites”, they write, “can thereby provide for high regulatory diversity, thus adding another level of complexity to gene-specific control” (Geserick et al. 2005).
The influence of form works in the other direction as well: the bound protein can transform the shape of DNA in a decisive way, making it easier for a second protein to bind nearby, even without any direct protein-protein interactions. In the case of one gene relating to the production of interferon (an important constituent of the immune system), “eight proteins modulate [DNA] binding site conformation and thereby stabilize cooperative assembly without significant contribution from interprotein interactions” (Moretti et al. 2008). As a result of this intricate cooperation of proteins and DNA in shifting the structure of the double helix, the cell achieves proper expression of the interferon gene according to its needs.
And so, despite the fact that “DNA is often mistakenly viewed as an inert lattice” onto which proteins bind in a sequence-specific way (Chaires 2008), the fact of the matter is altogether different. Proteins and DNA are caught up in a continual conversation of mutual influence and qualitative transformation.
On yet another front: the genetic code consists of sixty-four distinct codons, representing all the unique ways four different letters can be arranged in three-letter sequences. Because there are only twenty amino acid constituents of human protein, the code is redundant: several different codons can signify the same amino acid. Such codons have been considered “synonymous”, since the meaning of the code was originally thought to be exhausted in the specification of amino acids. However, biologists have steadily been discovering how non-equivalent these synonymous codons really are.
“Synonymous mutations [that is, changes of codons into different, yet synonymous, forms] do not alter the encoded protein, but they can influence gene expression”, Grzegorz Kudla and his colleagues write in Science magazine. To demonstrate the situation, these scientists engineered 154 versions of a gene — versions that differed randomly from each other, but only in synonymous ways. So all 154 genes still coded for the same protein.
They found that, in the bacterium Escherichia coli, these genes differed in expression, with the highest-expressing form producing 250 times as much protein as the lowest-expressing form. Bacterial growth rates also varied. The researchers determined that the choice of synonymous codons affected the folding structure of the resulting RNA transcripts, and this structure then affected the rate of RNA translation into protein (Kudla et al. 2009).
“Synonymous” in the narrow terms of code does not mean “synonymous” so far as the molecular sinews of life are concerned.
Finally and most generally: scientists using computers to scan the several billion nucleotide bases of the human genome in the search for significant features, have more and more been using sequence variations as indicators of sculptural and dynamic form at different scales. That’s because scans based on sequence alone, abstracted from physical form, have failed to find many of the regulatory elements that now appear so crucial to our understanding of genomic functioning. This search is leading to rapid discovery of new functional aspects of the formerly one-dimensional genome.
It’s also producing a growing awareness that what we inherit (and what makes a difference to evolution) is as much a matter of three-dimensional structure as it is of nucleotide sequence. Researchers have wondered why the sequences of many functional elements in DNA are not kept more or less constant by natural selection. The standard doctrine has it that functionally important sequences, precisely because they are important to the organism, will generally be conserved across considerable evolutionary distances.
But the emerging point of view holds that architecture can matter as much as sequence. As bioinformatics researcher Elliott Margulies and his team at the National Human Genome Research Institute put it, “the molecular shape of DNA is under selection” — a shape that can be maintained in its decisive aspects despite changes in the underlying sequence. It’s not enough, they write, to analyze “the order of A’s, C’s, G’s, and T’s“ because “DNA is a molecule with a three-dimensional structure” (Parker et al. 2009). Elementary as the point may seem, it’s leading to a considerable reallocation of investigative resources.
Of course, researchers knew all along that DNA and chromatin were spatial structures. But that didn’t prevent them from ignoring the fact as far as possible. Opportunities to pursue the abstract and determinate lawfulness of a code or mathematical rule have always shown great potential for derailing the scientist’s attention from the world’s full-bodied presentation of itself. Achieving logical and mathematical certainty within a limited sphere can seem more rigorously scientific than giving attention to the metamorphoses of form and rhythms of movement so intimately associated with life. These latter require more aesthetically informed cognitive capacities, and they put us at greater risk of having to acknowledge the evident expressive and highly concerted organization of living processes. When you encounter the meaningful, directed, and well-shaped movements of a dance, it’s hard to ignore the active principle — some would say the agency or being — coordinating the movements.
And nowhere do we find the dance more evident than in the focal performance of the nucleosome.
I have referred to nucleosomes as consisting of spool-like cores, made up of histone proteins, together with the DNA that is wrapped around them. But the so-called spools are not at all like the smooth cylinders one all too easily pictures. The image of an irregularly shaped pine cone might be more appropriate. Hundreds of distinct points of contact, with countless possible variations, define the relationship between the histone proteins of the core particle and the approximately two turns of associated DNA. We saw above how this relationship affects access to the DNA by the transcription factors that bind to it — factors that can promote or repress gene expression. One aspect of the dynamic has to do with the electrical forces that come into play between the positively charged histone surfaces and the (mostly) negatively charged outer regions of the double helix.
Here it is well to remember one of the primary lessons of twentieth-century physics: we are led disastrously astray when we try to imagine atomic- and molecular-level entities as if they were tiny bits of the stuff of our common experience. The histone core particle of nucleosomes, for example, is not some rigid thing. It would be far better to think of its “substance”, “surface”, “contact points”, and “physical interactions” as forms assumed by mutually interpenetrating forces in their intricate and infinitely varied play.
In any case, the impressive enactments of form and force about the nucleosome are surely central to any understanding of genes. The nucleosome is rather like a maestro directing the genetic orchestra, except that the directing is itself orchestrated by the surrounding cellular audience in conversation with the instrumentalists. The nucleosome is simply where the conversation comes to what may be its most vivid focus. In order to get a sense for the shape of the exchange, you will need a few details.
The canonical nucleosome core particle is a complex of histone proteins, each of which has a flexible, filamentary "tail". This tail can be modified through the addition of several different chemical groups — acetyl, methyl, phosphate, ubiquitin, and so on — at any of various locations along its length. A great variety of enzymes can apply and remove these chemical groups, and the groups themselves play a role in attracting a stunning array of gene regulatory proteins that restructure chromatin or otherwise help choreograph the drama of gene expression.
After a few histone tail modifications were found to be rather distinctly associated with active or repressed genes, the forlorn hope arose that we would discover a precise, combinatorial “histone code”. It would provide a fixed and reliable key enabling us to predict the consequences of any arrangement of modifications (Strahl and Allis 2000).
But this was to ignore the nearly infinite variety of all those contextual factors that blend their voices in concert with the histone modifications. In the plastic organism, what goes on at the local level is always shaped and guided by a larger, coherent context — a context that surely has meaning, but (as in all natural languages) never an absolutely fixed grammar. And, in fact, while overwhelming evidence for a meaningful, gene-regulatory conversation involving histone modifications has emerged, there is little to suggest a rigid code. Shelley Berger of Philadelphia’s Wistar Institute, noting that a single tail modification “recruits numerous proteins whose regulatory functions are not only activating but also repressing” and that “many of these marks have several, seemingly conflicting roles”, summarized the situation this way:
Although [histone] modifications were initially thought to be a simple code, a more likely model is of a sophisticated, nuanced chromatin ‘language’ in which different combinations of basic building blocks yield dynamic functional outcomes. (Berger 2007)
And (leaving aside the jarring reference to building blocks) how could it be otherwise? Each histone tail modification re-shapes the physical and electrical structure of the local chromatin, shifting the pattern of interactions among nucleosome, DNA, and associated protein factors. To picture this situation concretely — as opposed to remaining within the straightjacket of code — is immediately to realize that it cannot be captured in purely digital terms. A sculptor does not try to assess the results of a stroke of the hammer as a choice among the possibilities of a digital logic. Berger envisions histone modifications as participating in “an intricate ‘dance’ of associations”.
There is much much more. The histones making up a nucleosome core particle can themselves be exchanged for noncanonical, or variant histones, which also have recognizable — but not strictly encoded — relations to gene expression. Histones can even be removed from a core particle altogether, leaving it “incomplete”. And certain energy-expending proteins can slide core particles along the DNA, changing their position. We saw above that a shift of position by as little as two or three base pairs can mark the difference between gene activation or repression, as can changes in the rotational orientation of the DNA on the face of the histone core particle. And finally (to artificially limit our consideration): the tails — no doubt depending at least in part on the various modifications and protein associations mentioned earlier — can thread themselves through the encircling double helix, perhaps either loosening it from the core particle or holding it more firmly in place. But some of those same tails are also thought to establish nucleosome-to-nucleosome contacts, helping to compact a stretch of chromatin and repress gene expression.
Everything depends on contextual configurations that we can reasonably assume are as complex, nuanced, and expressively manifold as the gestural configurations available to a stage actor. Further, the nucleosome positioning pattern and other dynamics vary throughout a genome depending on tissue type, stage of the cell life cycle, and the wider physiological environment. They vary between genes that are more or less continuously expressed and those whose expression level changes with environmental conditions (Tirosh and Barkai 2008; Choi and Kim 2009). They vary between open chromatin and gene-repressive condensed chromatin. And they vary for any one gene as the actual process of transcription takes place — this because appropriate DNA regulatory sequences must become nucleosome-free before transcription can start, and also because DNA in the body of the gene must be disengaged from nucleosome core particles as the transcribing enzyme passes along, only to be (often) re-engaged behind the enzyme.
Seemingly in the grip of the encircling DNA with its relatively fixed and stable structure, yet responsive to the ceaselessly varying flows of life around it, the nucleosome holds the balance between gene and context — a task requiring flexibility, a “sense” of appropriate rhythm, and perhaps we could even say “grace".
Nucleosomes will sometimes move — or be moved (the distinction between actor and acted upon is forever obscured in the living cell) — rhythmically back and forth along the DNA, shifting between alternative positions in order to enable multiple transcription passes over a gene. In stem cells a process some have called “histone modification pulsing” results in the continual application and removal of both gene-repressive and gene-activating modifications of nucleosomes. In this way a delicate balance is maintained around genes involved in development and cell differentiation. The genes are kept, so to speak, in a finely poised state of “suspended readiness”, so that when the decision to specialize is finally taken, the repressive modifications can be quickly lifted, leading to rapid gene expression (Gan et al. 2007).
This state of suspended readiness in stem cells also seems to be served by a rhythmical (10 – 100 cycles per second), back-and-forth spatial movement, or vibration, of chromatin within the cell nucleus. Associated with “hyperdynamic binding of structural proteins” mediated by nucleosomes, this vibration is thought to help maintain the largely open chromatin state characteristic of stem cells. The movement depends on the metabolic state of the cell and is progressively dampened as the stem cell differentiates into a specialized cell (Hinde 2012) with substantial portions of its chromatin in a closed (heterochromatic) state.
But quite apart from stem cells, it is increasingly appreciated that nucleosomes play a key role in holding a balance between the active and repressed states of many genes. As the focus of a highly dynamic conversation involving histone variants, histone tail modifications, and innumerable chromatin-associating proteins, decisively placed nucleosomes can (as biologist Bradley Cairns writes) maintain genes “poised in the repressed state”, and “it is the precise nature of the poised state that sets the requirements for the transition to the active state”. Among other aspects of the dynamism, there is continual turnover of the nucleosomes themselves — and of their separate components — a turnover that allows transcription factors to gain access to DNA sequences “at a tuned rate” (Cairns 2009).
With another sort of rhythm the DNA around a nucleosome core particle “breathes”, alternately pulling away from the core particle and then reuniting with it, especially near the points of entry and exit. This provides what are presumably well-gauged, fractional-second opportunities for gene-regulating proteins to bind to their target DNA sequences during the periods of relaxation.
During the actual process of transcription, RNA polymerase appears to take advantage of this breathing in order to move, step by step and with significant pauses, along the gene it is transcribing. The characteristics of nucleosomes — whether firmly anchored to the DNA or easily dislodged — affect the timing and frequency of these pauses. And the rhythm of pauses and movements in turn affects the folding of the RNA being synthesized: a proper music is required for correct folding, which finally in its turn may affect the structure and function of the protein produced from the RNA molecule. The elements all respond to each other in a seamless dance of life.
Such, then, is the sort of intimate, intricate, well-timed choreography through which our genes come to their proper expression. And the plastic, shape-shifting nucleosome in the middle of it all — with its exquisite sensitivity to the DNA sequence on the one hand, and, on the other hand, its mobile, flexible tails responding fluidly to the ever-varying signals coming from the surrounding life context — provides an excellent vantage point from which to view the overall drama of form and movement.
Of all the broad topics comprising the field of genetic and epigenetic research, we have looked at very few — and perhaps not even the ones most dramatically undermining the doctrine that “genes are mechanisms of destiny”. But it is enough, I hope, to suggest why researchers are so energized and excited today. A sense of profound change seems to be widespread.
The one decisive lesson I think we can draw from the work in molecular genetics over the past couple of decades is that life does not progressively contract into a code or mechanism or any other reduced “building block” as we probe its more minute dimensions. Trying to define the chromatin complex, according to geneticists Shiv Grewal and Sarah Elgin (2007), “is like trying to define life itself”. Having plunged headlong toward the micro and molecular in their drive to reduce the living to the inanimate, biologists now find unapologetic life staring back at them from every chromatogram, every electron micrograph, every gene expression profile. Things do not become simpler, less organic, less animate. The explanatory task at the bottom is essentially the same as what we faced higher up. It’s rather our understanding that all too easily becomes constricted as we move downward, because the contextual scope and qualitative richness of our survey is so extremely narrowed.
The search for precise explanatory mechanisms and codes leads us along a path of least resistance toward the reduction of understanding. A capacity for imagination (not something many scientists are trained for today) is always required for grasping a living context in meaningful terms, because at the contextual level the basic data are not things, but rather relations, movement, and transformation. To see the context is to see a dance, not merely the bodies of the individual dancers.
The hopeful thing is that molecular biologists today — slowly but surely, and perhaps despite themselves — are increasingly being driven to enlarge their understanding through a reckoning with genetic contexts. As a result, they are writing “finis” to the misbegotten hope for a non-lifelike and mechanistic foundation of life, even if the fact hasn’t yet been widely announced.
It is, I think, time for the announcement.
There is a frequently retold story about a little old lady who claims, after hearing a scientific lecture, that the world is a flat plate resting on the back of a giant tortoise. When asked what the turtle is standing on, she invokes a second turtle. And when the inevitable follow-up question comes, she replies, “You’re very clever, young man, but you can’t fool me. It’s turtles all the way down”.
As a metaphor for the scientific understanding of biology, the story is marvelously truthful. In the study of organisms, “It’s life all the way down”.
Tags: chromosome/chromatin; chromosome/dynamics; chromosome/in 3D space; DNA; DNA/noncoding; epigenetics; explanation/and causation; gene/genocentrism; gene regulation; genomic_hype; holism; holism/organism as a formed stream; machine idea/code;
1. (Note added in 2015:) The exceptions, as it happens, have been multiplying considerably over the past few years.
Albrethsen, Jakob, Jaco C. Knol and Connie R. Jimenez (2009). “Unravelling the Nuclear Matrix Proteome”, Journal of Proteomics vol. 72, no. 1 (Feb. 15), pp. 71-81. doi:10.1016/j.jprot.2008.09.005
Berger, Shelley L. (2007). “The Complex Language of Chromatin Regulation During Transcription”, Nature vol. 447 (May 24), pp. 407-12. doi:10.1038/nature05915
Brown, Valerie (2008). “Environment Becomes Heredity” (July 14), available online at http://www.miller-mccune.com/article/environment-becomes-heredity
Cairns, Bradley R. (2009). “The Logic of Chromatin Architecture and Remodelling at Promoters”, Nature vol. 461 (Sep. 10), pp. 193-8. doi:10.1038/nature08450
Cavellán, Eric (2006). “Chromatin Remodelling in Pol I and III Transcription”, thesis, Universitet Stockholms. Doctoral thesis, available at http://su.diva-portal.org/smash/record.jsf?searchId=2&pid=diva2:200808
Chaires, Jonathan B. (2008). “Allostery: DNA Does It Too”, ACS Chemical Biology vol. 3, no. 4 (epublication: April 18), pp. 207-8. doi:10.1021/cb800070s
Choi, Jung Kyoon and Young-Joon Kim (2009). “Intrinsic Variability of Gene Expression Encoded in Nucleosome Positioning Sequences”, Nature Genetics (advance epublication: Mar. 1). doi:10.1038/ng.319
Couzin-Frankel, Jennifer (2009). “The Promise of a Cure: 20 Years and Counting”, Science vol. 324 (June 19), pp. 1504-7. doi:10.1126/science.324_1504.
Chuang, Chien-Hui, Anne E. Carpenter, Beata Fuchsova, et al. (2006). “Long-range Directional Movement of an Interphase Chromosome Site”, Current Biology vol. 16 (Apr. 18), pp. 825-31. doi:10.1016/j.cub.2006.03.059
Dineen, David G., Andreas Wilm, Pádraig Cunningham and Desmond G. Higgins (2009). “High DNA Melting Temperature Predicts Transcription Start Site Location in Human and Mouse”, Nucleic Acids Research vol. 37, no. 22, pp. 7360-7. doi:10.1093/nar/gkp821
Dumont, Jacques E., Fréderic Pécasse and Carine Maenhaut (2001). “Crosstalk and Specificity in Signalling: Are We Crosstalking Ourselves into General Confusion?”, Cellular Signalling vol. 13, pp. 457-63.
Gan, Qiong, Tadashi Yoshida, Oliver G. McDonald et al. (2007). “Concise Review: Epigenetic Mechanisms Contribute to Pluripotency and Cell Lineage Determination of Embryonic Stem Cells”, Stem Cells vol. 25, no. 1, pp. 2-9. doi:10.1634/stemcells.2006-0383
Geserick, Christoph, Hellmuth-Alexander Meyer and Bernard Haendler (2005). “The Role of DNA Response Elements as Allosteric Modulators of Steroid Receptor Function”, Molecular and Cellular Endocrinology vol. 236, no. 1-2 (May 31), pp. 1-7. doi:10.1016/j.mce.2005.03.007
Gilbert, Walter (1992). “A Vision of the Grail”, in The Code of Codes: Scientific and Social Issues in the Human Genome Project, edited by Daniel J. Kevles and Leroy Hood, pp. 83-97. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Göndör, Anita and Rolf Ohlsson (2009). “Chromosome Crosstalk in Three Dimensions”, Nature vol. 461 (Sep. 10), pp. 212-7. doi:10.1038/nature08453
Grewal, Shiv I. S. and Sarah C. R. Elgin (2007). “Transcription and RNA Interference in the Formation of Heterochromatin”, Nature vol. 447 (May 24), pp. 399-406. doi:10.1038/nature05914
Hecht, Jeff (2003). “Chimps Are Human, Gene Study Implies”, New Scientist (May 19). Available at http://newscientist.com/article/dn3744-chimps-are-human-gene-study-implies.html
Hinde, Elizabeth, Francesco Cardarelli, Aaron Chen et al. (2012). “Tracking the Mechanical Dynamics of Human Embryonic Stem Cell Chromatin”, Epigenetics and Chromatin vol. 5, no. 20. doi:10.1186/1756-8935-5-20
Kouzine, Fedor, Suzanne Sanford, Zichrini Elisha-Feil, et al. (2008). “The Functional Response of Upstream DNA to Dynamic Supercoiling in Vivo”, Nature Structural and Molecular Biology vol. 15, no. 2 (Feb.), pp. 146-54. doi:10.1038/nsmb.1372
Kudla, Grzegorz, Andrew W. Murray, David Tollervey and Joshua B. Plotkin (2009). “Coding-sequence Determinants of Gene Expression in Escherichia coli”, Science vol. 324 (April 10), pp. 255-8. doi:10.1126/science.1170160
Lavelle, Christophe (2009). “Forces and Torques in the Nucleus: Chromatin under Mechanical Constraints”, Biochemistry and Cell Biology vol. 87, pp. 307-22. doi:10.1139/O08-123
Lillie, F. R. (1927). “The Gene and the Ontogenetic Process”, Science vol. 46, pp. 361-8.
Martinez-Campa, Carlos, Panagiotis Politis, Jean-Luc Moreau, et al. (2004). “Precise Nucleosome Positioning and the TATA Box Dictate Requirements for the Histone H4 Tail and the Bromodomain Factor Bdf1”, Molecular Cell vol. 15 (July 2), pp. 69-81. doi:10.1016/j.molcel.2004.05.022
McCabe, Linda L. and Edward R. B. McCabe, DNA: Promise and Peril. Berkeley CA: Univ. of Calif. Press, 2008. I take the quotation from a book review, “Epigenetic Determinism”, by Michael A. Goldman, Science vol. 325, p. 816. doi:10.1126/science.1175293
Meijsing, Sebastiaan H., Miles A. Pufall, Alex Y. So et al. (2009). “DNA Binding Site Sequence Directs Glucocorticoid Receptor Structure and Activity”, Science vol. 324 (April 17), pp. 407-10. doi:10.1126/science.1164265
Misteli, Tom (2007). “Beyond the Sequence: Cellular Organization of Genome Function”, Cell vol. 128 (Feb. 23), pp. 787-800. doi:10.1016/j.cell.2007.01.028
Moretti, Rocco, Leslie J. Donato, Mary L. Brezinski et al. (2008). “Targeted Chemical Wedges Reveal the Role of Allosteric DNA Modulation in Protein-DNA Assembly”, ACS Chemical Biology vol. 3, no. 4 (epublication April 18). doi:10.1021/cb700258r
Osborne, Cameron S., Lyubomira Chakalova, Karen E. Brown et al. (2004). “Active Genes Dynamically Colocalize to Shared Sites of Ongoing Transcription”, Nature Genetics vol. 36, no. 10 (Oct.), pp. 1065-71. doi:10.1038/ng1423
Parker, Stephen C. J., Loren Hansen, Hatice Ozel Abaan et al. (2009). “Local DNA Topography Correlates with Functional Noncoding Regions of the Human Genome”, Science vol. 324 (April 17), pp. 389-92. doi:10.1126/science.1169050
Pearson, Helen (2009). “One Gene, Twenty Years”, Nature vol. 460, no. 7252 (July 9), pp. 165-9. doi:10.1038/460164a
Poulter, M., L. Du, I. Weaver, et al. (2009). “GABAA Receptor Promoter Hypermethylation in Suicide Brain: Implications for the Involvement of Epigenetic Processes”, Biological Psychiatry vol. 64, no. 8, pp. 645-52. doi:10.1016/j.biopsych.2008.05.028
Riordan, J. R., J. M. Rommens, B. Kerem et al. (1989). “Identification of the Cystic Fibrosis Gene: Cloning and Characterization of Complementary DNA”, Science vol. 245, no. 4922 (Sep. 8), pp. 1066-73.
Rohs, Remo, Sean M. West, Alona Sosinsky et al. (2009). “The Role of DNA Shape in Protein-DNA Recognition”, Nature vol. 461 (Oct. 29), pp. 1248-53. doi:10.1038/nature08473
Simonis, Marieke, Petra Klous, Erik Splinter, et al. (2006). “Nuclear Organization of Active and Inactive Chromatin Domains Uncovered by Chromosome Conformation Capture-on-chip (4C)”, Nature Genetics vol. 38, no. 11 (Nov.), pp. 1348-54. doi:10.1038/ng1896
Strahl, B. D. and C. D. Allis (2000). “The Language of Covalent Histone Modifications”, Nature vol. 403, no. 6765 (Jan 6), pp. 41-5. doi:10.1038/47412
Tirosh, Itay and Naama Barkai (2008). “Two Strategies for Gene Regulation by Promoter Nucleosomes“, Genome Research vol. 18, pp. 1084-91. doi:10.1101/gr.076059.108
Travers, Andrew and Georgi Muskhelishvili (2007). “A Common Topology for Bacterial and Eukaryotic Transcription Initiation?” EMBO Reports vol. 8, no. 2, pp. 147-51. doi:10.1038/sj.embor.7400898
Tullius, Tom (2009). “DNA Binding Shapes Up”, Nature vol. 461 (Oct. 29), pp. 1225-6. doi:10.1038/4611225a
Wachsmuth, Malte, Maïwen Caudron-Herger and Karsten Rippe (2008). “Genome Organization: Balancing Stability and Plasticity”, Biochimica et Biophysica Acta vol. 1783, no. 11 (Nov.), pp. 2061-2079. doi:10.1016/j.bbamcr.2008.07.022
Woelfle, Mark A., Yao Xu, Ximing Qin et al. (2007). “Circadian Rhythms of Superhelical Status of DNA in Cyanobacteria”, PNAS vol. 104, no. 47, pp. 18819-24. doi:10.1073/pnas.0706069104
This document: https://bwo.life/mqual/genome_4.htm
Steve Talbott :: Getting Over the Code Delusion